Tuesday, September 22, 2015

Bentham’s theory of utility.

4) Q. The principle of utility has penetrated from time to time into laws, from its

occasional alliance with the principle of sympathy and antipathy?  In the light of this

discuss Bentham’s theory of utility.

Q. “The pain or pleasure, which is attached to a law from what is called its sanction”.

Bentham.  Critically examine the four classes of sanctions laid down by  Bentham.

Q.  What is principle of Utility?  What is its use in a penal legislation?  Explain by giving

specific examples.

Q.  What is the principle of sympathy and antipathy?  Explain.

1. INTRODUCTION.

Utilitarianism –a philosophical movement flourished in 19th century in

England and, converts to countries with English flavour. In England

legal positivism was ushered by Thomas Hobbes and then by Jeremy

Bentham. Both of them correlated law with sovereignty and utility.

Bentham destroyed and demolished natural law giving currency to

the concept of utility as the principle of the ‘greatest good of the

greatest number’ - has condemned law of nature as ‘nothing but a

phrase’ and Blockstonian natural rights as ‘non-sense’ and eulogized

the doctrine of utility by rejecting both natural law and subjective

values and replacing these by standards based on human

advantages, pleasures and satisfactions.  Bentham was a believer in

laissez-faire. His emphasis on reform and social welfare has made

him one of the creators of the welfare state.  Bentham’s analysis of

the law has to be approached through his theory of fictions, which in

modern terminology would be styled semantics.

A law as distinct from law was to him a real entity, and so was an act.

Rights and duties, on the other hand, were fictional.

Basically, Bentham was interested in law of reforms.

The science of legislation is a branch of morals,  being the principles

upon which man’s actions are to be directed to the greatest quantity

of possible happiness.  The greatest happiness of the greatest

number might, require the greatest misery of the few.  This is well

brought out in Bentham’s  scheme for prison reform by way of his

celebrated “Panopticon.”

UTILITY-ITS MEANING:-

By the principle of utility is meant that principle which approves

or disapproves of every action whatever, according to the tendency

which it appears to have to augment or diminish the happiness of the

party whose interest is in question. or, what is the same thing in other words, to

promote or to oppose that happiness. I say of every action whatsoever; and therefore not

only of every action of a private individual, but of every measure of government.

Bentham: The Principle of Utility, also known as the “the greatest happiness

principle” (a term which he borrowed from Hume), is the belief that the best course of

action is whatever causes the greatest happiness for the greatest number of people.

Utilitarianism is the belief that what is best for society is whatever creates the greatest

amount of happiness for the greatest number of people. According to Bentham, each and

every person in a society is morally obligated to do that which causes the greatest amount

of happiness for everyone in the society. The principle of utility says that good actions

are the ones that create the most of happiness for the greatest number of people.

          Nature has placed mankind under the governance of two sovereign masters, pain

and pleasure. It is for them alone to point out what we ought to do, as well as to

determine what we shall do. On the one hand the standard of right and wrong, on the

other the chain of causes and effects, are fastened to their throne. They govern us in all

we do, in all we say, in all we think: every effort we can make to throw off our

subjection, will serve but to demonstrate and confirm it. In words, a man may pretend to

abjure their empire: but in reality he will remain subject to it all the while. The principle

of utility  recognises this subjection, and assumes it for the foundation of that system, the

object of which is to rear the fabric of felicity by the hands of reason and of law. Systems

which attempt to question it, deal in sounds instead of sense, in caprice instead of reason,

in darkness instead of light.

By the principle of utility is meant that principle which approves or disapproves

of every action whatsoever, according to the tendency which it appears to have to

augment or diminish the happiness of the party whose interest is in question: or, what is

the same thing in other words, to promote or to oppose that happiness. I say of every

action whatsoever; and therefore not only of every action of a private individual, but of

every measure of government.

If that party should be a particular individual, then the principle

of utility is designed to promote his happiness; if it should be the

community, then the principle contemplates the happiness of the

community.

Bentham emphasized that community can have no interests

independent of the interests of the individual.  To him community

interest is “the sum of the interest of the several members who

compose it”.

What is the same thing in other words, ‘promote or to oppose

the happiness’.  I say of every action, not only of a private individual,

but of every measure of government.

The Benthamite legislator must strive to attain the four

goals:-

i. Subsistence;

ii. Abundance;

iii. Equality; and

iv.  security for the citizens.

“All the functions of law” said Benthan, “ may be referred

to these four heads. Of these four ends of legal regulation, security

was to him the principal and paramount one.  Security demands

that a man’s person, his honour, his property and his status be

protected, and his expectations,  insofar as the law itself had

produced them, be maintained.  Liberty must sometimes yield to a

consideration of general security, since laws cannot be made except

at the expense of liberty.

The public good ought to be the object of the legislator and

general utility ought to be the foundation of his reasoning.

  To know the true good of the community is what constitute the

science of legislation - finding the means to realize that good.

Nature has placed mankind under the governance of two

sovereign maters, pain and pleasure.  It is for them alone to point out

what we ought to do, as well as to determine what we shall do.  On

the one hand the standards of right and wrong, on the other the chain

of causes and effects, are fastened to their throne. In words a man

may pretend to abjure their umpire; but in reality he will remain

subject to it all while.  The principle of utility recognized this

subjection, and assumes it for the foundation of that system, the

object of which is to rear the fabric of felicity by the hands of reason

and of law.  Utility is an abstract term.  It expresses the property or

tendency of a thing to prevent some evil or to procure some good.

Evil is pain or the cause of pain.  Good is pleasure or the cause of

pleasure.  That which is confirmable to the augment the total sum of

his happiness of the individual that compose it.  By utility is meant

that property in any object, whereby, it tends to produce benefit,

advantage, pleasure, good or happiness or to prevent the happening

of mischief, pain evil or unhappiness to the party whose interest is

considered; if that party be the community in general, the happiness

of the community if a particular individual, then the happiness of that

individual.

SOURCES OF PAIN AND PLEASURE

The  business of the government, according to Bentham, was to

promote the happiness of the society by furthering the enjoyment of

pleasure and affording security against pain. “It is the greatest

happiness of the greatest number that is the measure of right and

wrong”. He was convinced that if the individuals composing the

society were happy and contended, the whole body politic would

enjoy happiness and prosperity.

1. Security is the sole end which the legislator ought to have in

view;

2. The four sources from which pleasure and pain are in use to

flow: i. physical, ii. the political, iii. the moral, iv. and the

religious. Pleasures and pains belonging to each of them are

capable of giving a binding force to any law or rule of conduct,

they may all of them be termed sanctions.

3. If it be in the present life, and from the ordinary course of

nature, not purposely modified by the interposition of the will of

any human being, nor by any extraordinary interposition of any

superior invisible being, that the pleasure or the pain takes

place or is expected, it may be said to issue from or to belong

to be physical sanction.

4. If at the hands of a particular person or set of persons in the

community, who under names correspondent to that of judge,

are chosen for the particular purpose of dispensing it, according

to the will of the sovereign or supreme ruling power in the state,

it may be said to issue front the political sanction.

5. Of at the hands of such chance persons in the community, as

the party in question may happen in the course of his life to

have concerns with, according to each man’s spontaneous

disposition, and not according to any settled or concerted rule,

it may be said to issue from the moral or popular sanction.

6. If from the immediate hands of a superior invisible being, either

in the present life, or in future, it may be said to issue from the

religious sanction.

7. Pleasures and pains which may be expected to issue from the

physical, political or moral sanctions, must all of them be

expected to be experienced, if ever, in the present life; those

which can be expected to issue from the religious sanctions

may be expected to be experienced either in the present life or

in a further.

LAW AND SANCTIONS

At the very beginning of the first Chapter of his work of Laws in

General Bentham gives his initial definition of a law.  He continues:

“taking this definition for the standard, it matters not whether the

expression of will in question, so as it have put the authority of the

sovereign to back it, were by his immediate conception, or only by a

adaptation.” To this he later adds: “A will or mandate may be said to

belong to a sovereign in the way of conception when  it was he

himself who issued it and who first issued it, in the words or other

signs in which it stands expressed: it may be said to be long to him by

adoption when the person from whom it immediately emanates is not

the sovereign himself…..

The mandate which the sovereign in question is supposed to

adopt may be either already issued, or not in the former case it may

be said to be his by susception; in the latter by pre-adoption.

Bentham was  aware of the artificial and unrealistic results which

would ensure if the sovereign or sovereign body were said

specifically to produce and promulgate all the “Commands” or

“Orders’ of which the content of the positive law of a state made up.

His exposition therefore includes the idea that the sovereign,

thought directly responsible for originating some of the positive

law, also takes over to adopts orders given by other.  In

particular, the notion of “Pre-adoption” in one perhaps rather

unrefined way of expressing the forward-looking or purposive aspect

of legal authority.

For Austin the sanction is a vital part of the idea of law.  He

lays great emphasis on the  close interrelation of three elements in

law, namely, “command” duty and sanction.  These  are

inseparably connected terms; each embraces the same idea as the

others.

Bentham’s account admits both punishments and rewards,

which he calls respectively “ coercive motives” and “alluring motives”.

Austin, however, refuses to allow the terms “sanction” to be extended

to cover rewards: “I think that this extension of the term is pregnant

with confusion and perplexity.  The difference of opinion between

these two jurists is attributable, not to a difference in interpretation of

the term sanction itself, but rather to the relative lack of concern

shown by Bentham with the element of sanction in his concept of law.

Bentham pays more attention, however, to sanctions while discussing

methods of enforcement  of laws at a later stage in his work.

Bentham has made the classification of sanctions.  Though

not original indeed it well regarded as highly derivative.  But this

analysis of correlation among the different types of sanctions, and

policy guidance arising from this, is highly original, deserving close

guidance arising from this, is highly original, deserving close

examination.  The notion of sanction itself poses no analytical

problem to Bentham-such is the power of the principle of utility.  The

pain or pleasure” he says, which is attached to a law form what is

called a sanction”.  Implicit in this definition is an answer to the

question whether reward can be properly regarded as sanction.  Nor

does Bentham, rightly find it compelling, as so many have done, to

distinguish between positive and negative sanctions, the one

corresponding, roughly, to reward and the other to punishment

deprivation etc.  Since pleasures and pains may be

distinguished into four classes-physical, moral, political,

religious the sanctions also subdivide themselves accordingly.

Pleasures and pains “which may be expected in the ordinary

course of nature, without human intervention, compose the

natural or physical sanction” the term without human intervention

makes this distinctive definition somewhat problematic as Bentham’s

own  example illustrates.  If a man’s house s destroyed by fire as a

consequence of his imprudence.  Bentham would call it a plain

of natural sanction.”  But imprudence is not to be found in the

“ordinary course of nature and does definitely constitute human

intervention.  What does then Bentham really mean by natural

sanction?  The answer must be that it is a pain or pleasure

arising directly out of an event or an occurrence, regardless of

the factors which might have caused or contributed to the

occurrence or the event.  In this sense, the destruction of the house

by fire is painful; it is an event, with its consequences (fire, therefore,

destruction) which arise out of the ordinary course of nature.  Human

intervention (fire fighting) any operate as a source of pleasure; but

once again the actual pleasure will be derived not so much from the

act of fire-extinguishment but from the fact that fire is extinguished or

controlled.  For Bentham, this too would be an instance of a natural

sanction.  Moral sanction are pains and pleasures “expected

from the action of our fellow-men” in terms of their spontaneous

dispositions towards us” whether the latter  be of friendship or

hatred” esteem or contempt.  Bentham designates this sanction

as popular sanction or the sanction of sympathy.  More

commonly, he later simply refers, to popular sanctions. It must not

be assumed carelessly that Bentham necessarily equals morality with

public opinion or honour or sympathy.  Popular sanctions may

indeed often be most profoundly immoral from a specific ethical

standpoint e.g.  ostracism for not observing segregation

between the whites and blacks or for violating social distance

based on the axis of pollution and purity, between a high-caste

Hindu and an “untouchable.”

Legal sanctions - pleasures and pains which can be

“expected from the action of the magistrate in virtue of the

laws”.  Bentham describes them alternately as “political

sanctions,” thus seizing the vital fact that legislative decisions are

also products of political processes- the action of a magistrate need

not consist merely of punishment in the strict sense.  It may cover

diverse activities-such as upholding a transaction, declaring a will

valid or void, providing matrimonial relief, etc.

Religious sanctions are distinctive from social or moral

sanctions in the sense that the orientation of the actor is not towards

another social actor as such but towards some supernatural entity,

even when made manifest through a human being.  Pleasures and

pains arising from the religious orientation are described by

Bentham as constituting religious sanctions.

Only a small number of laws in a legal system relate

directly to the application of sanctions, especially if the notion of

a sanction is to be defined, with Austin, as a chance a threat of

some evil or harm.  Type of legal rule which most nearly

approximates to Austin’s model is a rule of criminal law which

requires that certain physical or material action be annexed to certain

behaviors.  Even then, however, the other essential elements in

Austin’s notion of law render his account inadequate as a proper

explanation of both theory and practice.  Bentham’s account admits

both punishments and rewards, which he calls respectively “coercive

motives” and “alluring motives”.  Austin however, refuses to allow the

term sanction to be extended to cover rewards; “I think that this

extension of the term is pregnant with confusion and perplexity”.  The

difference of opinion between these two jurists is attributable, not to a

difference in interpretation of the term, itself, but rather to the relative

lack of concern shown by Bentham with the element of sanction in his

concept of law.  Bentham pays more attention, however, to sanctions

when discussing methods of enforcement of laws at a later stage in

his work.

THE ASCETIC PRINCIPLE

The Ascetic Principle is the opposite or contrary to that

which we have just discussed.  The follower of this Principle have a

honour of the pleasures.  They are of the view that the thing which

gratifies the senses is criminal.  They find morality upon privations,

and virtue upon the renouncement of one’s self.  Therefore, in other

words, the opposite of the partisans of utility.  The followers of this

Principle approve everything which tend to diminish enjoyment

and blame everything which tend to augment the enjoyment.

The followers of this principle can be divided into two classes of why

in other respects have scarce any resemblance, and who even affect

a mutual contempt.  The philosophers and the devotees are the

followers of this principles.

The ascetic philosophers, animated by the hope of applause,

have flattered themselves with the idea of seeming to raise above

humanity, by despising vulgar pleasures.  They want to be paid in

reputation and glory for all the sacrifices which they seem to make to

the severity of their maxims.  The ascetic devotes are foolish people,

torments by vain terrors.  They consider man as a degenerate being

who ought to punish himself without ceasing for the crime of being

born, and never to turn off his thoughts from that gulf of eternal

misery which is ready to open beneath his feet.  The philosophers

have confined themselves to censuring pleasure; the religious sects

have turned the infliction of plain into duty.